Is Dawkins’ theory of kin selection sufficient to explain genetic altruism?

I

 

This article examines the theory of kin selection presented in Richard Dawkins’ ‘ The Selfish Gene’ and argues that his theory falls short in explaining genetic altruism; in particular, it emphasizes the importance of environmental factors and suggests the need to supplement existing theories.

 

Introduction

Richard Dawkins’ 1976 publication of The Selfish Gene introduced a new paradigm to the biological community about the nature of genes. His theory is as simple as the title suggests: “The primary goal of genes is to prosper (dominance in the gene pool), and this explains the selfish, exclusionary behavior of individuals.” Most people who first encounter Dawkins’ theory will question it, citing counterexamples of altruistic behavior. But Dawkins uses the mechanisms behind these altruistic behaviors to explore the source of genetic selfishness. Forty years later, advances in science have exposed many of the argumentative fallacies in Dawkins’s account. The most notable of these is Dawkins’ theory of kin selection. Dawkins provides a plausible explanation for altruism among individuals who share genes by using the gene’s nearness. This is a measure of how much genes are shared between individuals, and he uses it to explain kinship behavior. However, Dawkins’ explanation of kinship selection is incomplete, with many inconsistencies and counterexamples. In response, Dawkins evades explanation without clarification or acknowledgment of his incompleteness. This essay attempts to complement Dawkins’ explanation by using environmental determinism.

 

Dawkins’ kin selection theory and its problems

In explaining his theory of kin selection, Dawkins states his grand premise (genes try to leave as many copies as possible). When it comes to kinship (between individuals who share one or more genes), Dawkins talks about genes as if they behave purely computationally. Here’s how they calculate the genetic plausibility of their behavior When an individual performs an action, add up the benefits of the action, +, and the costs, -, and get the total. This is called the net benefit score, and the individual will act in the direction of the largest net benefit score. If they are not related, the benefit or harm of the behavior to individuals other than themselves is calculated as zero. Dawkins notes at the end that his explanations may be uncertain, leaving open the possibility that they may be based on estimates and experience, such as the certainty of nearness and the life expectancy of individuals. Dawkins also brings certainty and accuracy into the discussion of kinship selection by comparing the animals’ estimates of their age with those of naturalists and concluding that the “true” age of the animals is not as important as they thought it was.
However, there are many problems with Dawkins’ theory of kinship selection. First, it uses too few variables (closeness, certainty, and life expectancy). Second, he fails to provide a systematic and logical explanation for the counterexamples. First, the explanation of kin selection based on nearness is wrong. The calculation of nearness is too simple. It simply uses the generation gap and doesn’t take into account mutations or other genetic influences (early in development). In other words, you don’t know how much of your gene is in another individual, so you can’t act accordingly. It also raises questions about certainty. How would individuals with shared genes actually recognize each other if they were separated and hadn’t seen each other in a long time? Of course, humans have a concept of genealogy, but other animals don’t, so they wouldn’t recognize each other.
For example, if there are parents and children, Dawkins’ theory of kin selection explains why parents are good to their children, but how does it explain why children are good to their parents? Children often sacrifice themselves to help their parents, even though they have no genes to pass on to them and their parents have a lower life expectancy than they do. This is not unique to humans, and Dawkins’ theory of kin selection does not explain this situation. Dawkins also fails to answer many counterexamples. An example is the turtle egg, which can be considered from both the parent’s and the fake child’s perspective. From the parent’s point of view, the ability to accurately identify their own eggs from those of others would be necessary for genetic prosperity. However, if this mechanism is not properly developed, the egg will be fooled until it awakens. This is a great genetic loss, and it can be said that genes are not capable of organized kin selfishness.
Conversely, from the child’s (and indeed the parent’s) perspective, having a child lay eggs in the wrong nest is a loss compared to raising them yourself, given the possibility of the eggs breaking. Even if the number of children one has is large, laying eggs is a sacrifice of one’s own individuality for the sake of an uncertain entity (descendants), and is therefore selfish. This phenomenon is a counterexample to Dawkins’s theory of kin selection, which he fails to recognize and insensitively dismisses. Another example is moral behavior, which, even if limited to humans, requires logical proof rather than avoiding the answer by using the word “society,” even if social pressures and education exist for humans. It is unclear how traveling to Africa to volunteer (assuming there is no benefit) would benefit one’s own genetic prosperity.

 

Complementing the theory of kin selection

Above, we’ve identified the problems with Dawkins’ theory of kin selection. It shows that we can’t simply rely on kinship alone to explain an individual’s behavior. The environment in which an individual lives must also be added to the theory of kinship selection in order to address some of its incompleteness. An individual’s behavior is a combination of both kinship and environmental factors. For example, an imprinted person who believes and follows a parent even though they are not related to him or her is more influenced by the environment in which he or she was born than by genes. In humans, adoption is also impossible to explain solely by blood. Adopted children and their parents don’t share a single drop of blood, yet many parents do everything they can for their adopted children. It’s their love for the child, not their genes. These behaviors vary from person to person, from individual to individual, and are so hard to quantify that they cannot be calculated. Dawkins would have to accept that there are environmental factors that cannot be calculated into existing theories. In other words, Dawkins can stick to his theory if there are no environmental influences, but if there are any, he will have to accept them.
Furthermore, more research is needed to understand how environmental factors affect genetic behavior. For example, differences in parenting behavior or social structure in different animal species could be studied to understand how environmental factors affect the behavior of genes. This would complement Dawkins’ theory and contribute to a more comprehensive explanation. Furthermore, the complex moral behaviors and social norms in human societies can also be explained by the interaction between environment and genes.

 

Conclusion

In the previous section, we looked at Dawkins’ theory and how it fits into kin selection, listed the problems with his theory of kin selection (math accuracy, environmental factors), and provided counterexamples of the problems (e.g., fertility, adoption, imprinting). From this, we can conclude that Dawkins needs to account for the influence of the environment in his theory. We were unable to quantify the influence of the environment, but creative follow-up research may be able to explain the unified theory of behavior through quantification. While Dawkins’ theory remains an important foundation for biological research, it is important to recognize that it is not the only way to explain evolutionary behavior. Future research will complement Dawkins’ theory and contribute to building a more comprehensive and accurate theory of evolutionary behavior.

 

About the author

Blogger

Hello! Welcome to Polyglottist. This blog is for anyone who loves Korean culture, whether it's K-pop, Korean movies, dramas, travel, or anything else. Let's explore and enjoy Korean culture together!